Introduction
An
‘Open Letter’ or petition has been publicised calling on the Catholic Bishops
of Poland to withdraw their support for a legislative initiative to criminalise
all abortion. The signatures are arranged in alphabetical order, but the second
name, Tina Beattie, Professor of Catholic Studies at Roehampton, is one of the
very few which will be widely recognised, and it will be convenient to refer to
the document as ‘the Beattie Petition’. The text, purporting to come from
signatories who ‘respect the Church’s moral stance against abortion’, is a
disgraceful, but wholly unsuccessful, attempt to justify a failure to protect
the unborn. It’s central contention, that abortion is not always an act of
injustice towards innocent life deserving of legal protection, cannot overcome,
and only ignore, Pope St John Paul II’s powerful declaration the Church’s
infallible teaching on abortion, in his 1995 Encyclical Evanglium vitae §57:
Therefore, by the authority which
Christ conferred upon Peter and his Successors, and in communion with the
Bishops of the Catholic Church, I confirm that the direct and voluntary killing
of an innocent human being is always gravely immoral. This doctrine, based upon
that unwritten law which man, in the light of reason, finds in his own heart
(cf. Rom 2:14-15), is reaffirmed by Sacred Scripture, transmitted by the
Tradition of the Church and taught by the ordinary and universal Magisterium.
Before
analysing the Petition, it is well to consider what legislation can hope to
achieve on the subject of abortion. The answer is simple: the criminalisation
of abortion will reliably suppress the openly practiced, legal abortion
industry.
Abortion’s
proponents, including the Beattie Petition, invariably argue that ‘driving
abortion underground’ is of no benefit, but this is far from being the case.
Most obviously, in times and places where abortion has been illegal, but where
the availability of illegal abortion has been widely known, and efforts to
stamp out illegal abortion far from vigorous, the number of abortions actually
carried out has been very small compared with the number performed when
abortion has been decriminalised, even under apparently restrictive legal
regimes.
There
are in addition three other important benefits of criminalisation.
First,
the abortion industry’s legal existence creates permanent pressure for the
easing of restrictions on abortion, by its support for political campaigning in
favour of abortion; similarly, its existence acts as an advertisement of its
services, even if some forms of open advertisement are not permitted.
Second,
the abortion industry, as countless examples from around the world have
demonstrated in recent years, has scant regard for the legal limitations under
which it is supposed to operate, or for the safety of its clients. Indeed, it
is also a fallacy, exposed in the most painful manner by recent criminal
convictions in the United States that, unsafe and even illegal abortions, with
poorly trained abortionists and in unsanitary conditions, necessarily disappear
when abortion is legalised.
Third,
the existence of legal abortion is corrosive to the ethos of the medical
profession, whose training and practice is obliged to take account of abortion
as a supposedly legitimate procedure. In practice, where abortion is legal and
hospitals carry it out, administrators will put pressure on practioners to
perform this unpopular procedure, and will ensure that it is included in
medical training. A section, at least, of the medical profession will, often
against their will, necessarily become involved in abortion, and its putative
legitimacy will have to be taken into account in any discussion of medical
ethics, undermining a proper understanding of the role of the doctor in
relation to his or her patients, in the tradition of the Hippocratic Oath and
of Catholic teaching on the Natural Law.
II
The
central contention of the Beattie petition bears on another benefit of
criminalisation, which is the most important of all: its effect on women in
crisis pregnancies. The Petition claims:
We appreciate the complex ethical
challenges involved in any intentionally abortive act. However, we also believe
that our Catholic faith calls us to be attentive to suffering in all its forms,
and to respond with trust in the mercy, forgiveness and compassion of God when
faced with with [sic] profound moral dilemmas that offer no clear solution. In
situations where abortion is deemed necessary – such as those currently
permitted under Polish law – we believe that access to early, safe and legal
abortion is essential.
The
cases currently permitted by Polish law are those where a pregnancy is the
result of rape; where the mother’s life is endangered by the pregnancy; and
where the unborn child is severely disabled or terminally ill. It is these
cases alone which will be affected by a complete ban, and which are addressed
by the Beattie Petition.
It
is difficult to see ‘mercy, forgiveness, and compassion’ at work in the
decision to abort a disabled or sick child, particularly when the serious
psychological and physical dangers abortion, compared with childbirth, has for
mothers. Abortion is the preferred answer, rather, of a medical and social
system which would rather not be burdened by the task of supporting mothers and
their children in these difficult circumstances.
When
a child is conceived in rape, the motivation of the rape victim and her friends
and family in seeking abortion is easy to understand. It is equally clear,
however, that it can never be a healing choice for a mother to consent to the
destruction of her own child. The testimony of many women to the psychological
trauma caused by abortion does not encourage the view that abortion is an easy
way out for victims of rape.
The
Petition focuses, instead, on the case of mothers whose health in endangered by
continuing a pregnancy. In this case, the question arises of whether, in the
context of modern medicine, such cases actually occur. The 2012 Dublin
Declaration on Maternal Health states:
As experienced practitioners and
researchers in obstetrics and gynaecology, we affirm that direct abortion – the
purposeful destruction of the unborn child – is not medically necessary to save
the life of a woman.
This
has been signed by more than a thousand medical practioners. The Declaration
clearly distinguishes, as the Catholic moral tradition does, and as laws
restricting abortion typically do, between abortion, as a procedure aiming at
the death of an unborn child, and the medical treatment of a pregnant mother
which may endanger the child’s life. In the Catholic tradition, as in the law,
the latter can often be legitimate, taking account of the seriousness of the
threat to the mother, the possibility of alternative treatments, and so on.
III
The
Beattie Petition appeals to the tragic circumstances implied in each of these
cases, with the implication that offering the possibility of abortion is the
compassionate thing to do. For a mother in a crisis pregnancy, in some cases
traumatised by rape, in other cases seriously ill, or struggling to come to
terms with the news that her child is severely disabled, the offer of abortion
is not a compassionate intervention. When offered, perhaps with the
encouragement of doctors or family members, it will generally present itself as
a recommendation. Like all medical recommendations, it will in such
circumstances require a special strength of character to resist it,
particularly when accompanied by the implied threat: if you don’t abort, the
baby will remind you of the rape, the baby will be disabled, the baby will kill
you: claims which will not necessarily be true. Such recommendations may be
accompanied by pressure, of a subtle or not so subtle kind, from partners or
family members, who may for a variety of reasons prefer the baby not to exist. The
open door to abortion will distract the attention of all involved from the
alternative possibilities: of accepting the unique and sacred character of the
child’s life, and of coming to terms with the problems implied by the pregnancy
with the support of doctors, family members, and where appropriate the state.
Offering abortion to mothers in these cases can, in practice, be hard to
distinguish from dispatching them down a pathway of convenience for others, a
pathway in which the complications of a crisis pregnancy are swept aside, and
the mother is left to cope with the trauma of abortion instead, a trauma the
existence of which the advocates of abortion, like the signatories of the
Beattie Petition, do not wish even to acknowledge.
It
is precisely in these tragic circumstances, more so than in cases where
abortion is motivated by apparently frivolous considerations, that the reality
of abortion is apparent, as an injustice not only to the unborn, but to the
mother. Legal abortion opens up the most vulnerable women of all to pressure to
consent to a crime against their unborn child, and against themselves. The
criminalisation of abortion, as proposed today in Poland, is a step towards the
protection of women and the unborn alike.
IV
Two
other claims of the Beattie Petition should briefly be considered. First is the
claim that abortion could be reduced by greater availability of contraception:
Finally, there is a body of
evidence to show that the best way to prevent abortion is to respect women’s
human dignity and freedom of conscience with regard to reproductive decisions,
by guaranteeing access to reliable methods of birth control.
Such
evidence as is commonly cited is far from decisive, however; what is widely
observed and agreed is that the majority of women seeking abortion had been
using contraception. The connection between a contraceptive culture and the
demand for abortion was set out by Pope St John Paul II in Evangelium vitae (1995) §13. It is strange, in any case, that this
claim should be thought to have bearing on the cases of pregnancy resulting
from rape, or where abortion is suggested because an unborn child is disabled,
or the pregnancy is supposedly a danger to the mother’s life. However rare or
common such cases may be, reliable contraception is not going to prevent them
arising.
The
second claim is the alleged relevance of religious freedom, and Dignatatis humanae, the Declaration on
Religious Liberty of the Second Vatican Council, §2. This section deals with
the freedom to profess religious beliefs. Any understanding of religious
freedom must distinguish between the manifestation of beliefs in harmless ways,
and the alleged manifestation of religious beliefs in ways which are unjust to
others, particularly others who are do not, or cannot, consent to this
treatment. What is unjust must, in turn, necessarily be assessed objectively. Dignitatis humanae makes precisely this
distinction, in §7, and ignoring this fact is an indication of a lack of
intellectual integrity in the Beattie Petition:
The right to religious freedom is
exercised in human society: hence its exercise is subject to certain regulatory
norms. In the use of all freedoms the moral principle of personal and social
responsibility is to be observed. In the exercise of their rights, individual
men and social groups are bound by the moral law to have respect both for the
rights of others and for their own duties toward others and for the common
welfare of all. Men are to deal with their fellows in justice and civility.
As
a matter of fact, the Second Vatican Council directly addressed the issue of
abortion, in the Dogmatic Constitution Gaudium
et spes, §51, which stressed the obligation to guard against what is a crime,
and not just a private sin:
For God, the Lord of life, has
conferred on men the surpassing ministry of safeguarding life in a manner which
is worthy of man. Therefore from the moment of its conception life must be
guarded with the greatest care while abortion and infanticide are unspeakable
crimes.
The
Beattie Petition also includes an appeal to ‘the call to mercy and compassion mercy’
of Pope Francis. The petitioners can find no comfort, however, in the Holy
Father’s most recent publication, the Post-Synodal Exhortation Amoris Laetitia (2016) §83:
So great is the value of a human
life, and so inalienable the right to life of an innocent child growing in the
mother’s womb, that no alleged right to one’s own body can justify a decision
to terminate that life, which is an end in itself and which can never be
considered the “property” of another human being.
this is a really excellent article. I think it highlights well why having an abortion industry is not helpful towards women's health.
ReplyDeleteDon't know if you saw this http://blogs.bmj.com/medical-ethics/2012/12/05/double-effect-in-the-halappanavar-case/
ReplyDelete